I'm not that interested in pragmatism per se. My interest in William James is because of his radical empiricism, not really his pragmatism. But I do want to clarify some things here. I want to explain what pragmatism is (namely a method), and show how even though James and Peirce agree about the method of pragmatism, the understanding diverges significantly.
***
Few things were as bad of an idea as naming your philosophical movement pragmatism. I wonder how many objections and misunderstandings can be traced to how terrible of a name it is. According to EtymologyOnline the world pragmatic in the 1600s meant "meddlesome, impertinently busy," in other words, a busy body. Yeesh. More recently, of course, it doesn't get much better. A "pragmatist" is one who faces so-called hard truths, and doesn't let things like principles, ideals, or ethics get in the way. The vision and imagination of a pragmatist is taken to be quite small. That William James called himself a pragmatist, and an empiricist, that he described judging truth based on its "cash-value," and discussed how a "will to believe" could shape and change the truth--well, it's no surprise that many take James to be a figure like Dale Carnegie, or whomever wrote The Secret. Indeed, Max Horkheimer, in Eclipse of Reason, famously attacks pragmatism. He knows it is bad, but he can’t figure out if it’s bad because it’s too objective, trying to reduce all knowledge to laboratory experiments. Or is it bad because it’s too subjective, and can’t resist ideology on the basis of reality. When I posted this comment about Horkheimer on Facebook, many responded that the correct answer was both/and. Of course that is a great response, but I believe the only way to make it both is through a pragmatic understanding. So, let's talk briefly about what pragmatism is, and how it is a method or a tool.
The pragmatic maxim, as it is often called, is usually traced to C.S. Peirce's essay, "How to Make our Ideas Clear." There he states, "Consider what effects, that might conceivably have practical bearings, we conceive the object of our conception to have. Then, our conception of these effects is the whole of our conception of the object." Now Peirce is said to have regretted this exact formulation, and if you are interested, you should check on the discussion from Cheryl Misak The American Pragmatists, pp. 29-32. But for our purposes, this is good enough. Pragmatism is a method, by which we ask what are the practical consequences of any philosophical problem. If there are none, we are free to ignore the issue as a pseudo-problem.
Here is William James, in chapter 2 of his book Pragmatism, where he famously gives an example of how pragmatism works. In it, he presents a story of professors arguing over, what else, words. Here is the full, long example:
Some years ago, being with a camping party in the mountains, I returned from a solitary ramble to find everyone engaged in a ferocious metaphysical dispute. The corpus of the dispute was a squirrel—a live squirrel supposed to be clinging to one side of a tree-trunk; while over against the tree's opposite side a human being was imagined to stand. This human witness tries to get sight of the squirrel by moving rapidly round the tree, but no matter how fast he goes, the squirrel moves as fast in the opposite direction, and always keeps the tree between himself and the man, so that never a glimpse of him is caught. The resultant metaphysical problem now is this: DOES THE MAN GO ROUND THE SQUIRREL OR NOT? He goes round the tree, sure enough, and the squirrel is on the tree; but does he go round the squirrel? In the unlimited leisure of the wilderness, discussion had been worn threadbare. Everyone had taken sides, and was obstinate; and the numbers on both sides were even. Each side, when I appeared, therefore appealed to me to make it a majority. Mindful of the scholastic adage that whenever you meet a contradiction you must make a distinction, I immediately sought and found one, as follows: "Which party is right," I said, "depends on what you PRACTICALLY MEAN by 'going round' the squirrel. If you mean passing from the north of him to the east, then to the south, then to the west, and then to the north of him again, obviously the man does go round him, for he occupies these successive positions. But if on the contrary you mean being first in front of him, then on the right of him, then behind him, then on his left, and finally in front again, it is quite as obvious that the man fails to go round him, for by the compensating movements the squirrel makes, he keeps his belly turned towards the man all the time, and his back turned away. Make the distinction, and there is no occasion for any farther dispute. You are both right and both wrong according as you conceive the verb 'to go round' in one practical fashion or the other."
Altho one or two of the hotter disputants called my speech a shuffling evasion, saying they wanted no quibbling or scholastic hair-splitting, but meant just plain honest English 'round,' the majority seemed to think that the distinction had assuaged the dispute.
I tell this trivial anecdote because it is a peculiarly simple example of what I wish now to speak of as THE PRAGMATIC METHOD. The pragmatic method is primarily a method of settling metaphysical disputes that otherwise might be interminable. Is the world one or many?—fated or free?—material or spiritual?—here are notions either of which may or may not hold good of the world; and disputes over such notions are unending. The pragmatic method in such cases is to try to interpret each notion by tracing its respective practical consequences. What difference would it practically make to anyone if this notion rather than that notion were true? If no practical difference whatever can be traced, then the alternatives mean practically the same thing, and all dispute is idle. Whenever a dispute is serious, we ought to be able to show some practical difference that must follow from one side or the other's being right.
And as he will add just a little further down in the chapter, "No particular results then, so far, but only an attitude of orientation, is what the pragmatic method means. The attitude of looking away from first things, principles, 'categories,' supposed necessities; and of looking towards last things, fruits, consequences, facts."
The passage seems both obvious and banal at first glance. It simply seems to say that language's meaning is simply useful, rather than somehow the truth being inhered in the words themselves. There is no fundamental truth of a word's meaning outside of us. So, "around" can mean multiple things.
This might be obvious, but the implications are actually very controversial. Because James is not actually trying to say anything in particular about language. He is trying to to say something about truth, of which the use of words is but an example. So, what is James saying about truth?
He is saying the way to determine truth is it's usefulness in specific ways. This is the claim of pragmatism. Therefore, pragmatism becomes a system of verification. How do we decide what are the practical consequences? This issue of verification is where the whole system falls apart between James and Peirce.
For those of you who know the work of the logical empiricists (also known as the positivists or the Vienna Circle). Verification is at the center of their work. As Misak describes them, "Their positions were crisp and clear; their knowledge of logic and science was unassailable; they were driven by a sense of purpose and a mission to clean up the metaphysical squalor in which they thought philosophy lived; and they thought that progress is possible only if all inquiry is scientific." (p. 157) And they therefore believed that the "meaning of a concept lies in the operations of its verification." (p. 159). Now, I don't know the logical empiricists that well, and honestly share the biases against them articulated so well in Barry Allen's Empiricisms, chapter 7. But I think I am being accurate to say that Peircian pragmatism and the logical empiricists, despite their differences, lay down a series of tools that will inform American analytic philosophy, particularly in the work of Lewis, Sellars, and to a lesser degree, Quine. And the upshot of this strand of philosophy is to be metaphysically deflationary. To what degree changes from thinker to thinker, but the world shrinks. Verification means some combination of scientific experiment or formal logical verification. And anything that cannot be verified as such, is not in the domain of philosophy. The world, very much in the singular, is made safe for a scientific and materialist monism. This is about as far from James as one could get, so how does his verification change things?
Before going further, I want to push against how we group thinkers together. I was very convinced by Misak about the story she tells of Peirce, and his linage. If you are interested in this story of a kind of pragmatism playing a role in the foundation of analytic philosophy, I suggest reading Section III of her book. But I am not convinced by her story of James and his lineage. Misak essentially reads Rorty as being an extension of Jamesian pragmatism. And it is true that Rorty didn't much care for Peirce, and saw himself as being a Deweyian and to a lesser degree, a Jamesian. But I follow Alexis Dianda's excellent book, The Varieties of Experience here. Particularly in chapter one, she shows how the linguistic turn in philosophy, which includes both Sellars and Rorty here, displaces the centrality of experience. And in seeking to displace experience for, as Rorty wants, discourse, we make James' position on verification and pragmatism completely incoherent. Let's look at James' famous lines on verification from chapter 6 of Pragmatism:
Pragmatism, on the other hand, asks its usual question. "Grant an idea or belief to be true," it says, "what concrete difference will its being true make in anyone's actual life? How will the truth be realized? What experiences will be different from those which would obtain if the belief were false? What, in short, is the truth's cash-value in experiential terms?"
The moment pragmatism asks this question, it sees the answer: True ideas are those that we can assimilate, validate, corroborate and verify. False ideas are those that we cannot. That is the practical difference it makes to us to have true ideas; that, therefore, is the meaning of truth, for it is all that truth is known-as.
This thesis is what I have to defend. The truth of an idea is not a stagnant property inherent in it. Truth happens to an idea. It becomes true, is made true by events. Its verity is in fact an event, a process: the process namely of its verifying itself, its veri-fication. Its validity is the process of its valid-ation.
This is very different from the conception of verification as scientific experiment or formal logic. Indeed, that becomes but one process of verification and validation, rather than the process. Truth becomes something existential in James' formulation. When James argues that truth must make a difference, he means in our lives. But also his pragmatic method is not deflationary, but rather pluralistic.
James' system of verification and validation allows for a multiple ways of verifying something. If there are many processes that can arrive at different answers about if something is true, and there is no way to put these processes in some sort of hierarchy, we have utterly exploded the metaphysical possibilities of the world. We have therefore a multiverse, a pluriverse, a pluralistic universe (to use some of James' terms). The world is, as James puts it, "ultra-Gothic."
So, the scientific methods are all fine systems of verification. But there are others! For example, in Kandinsky's On the Spiritual in Art he gives us this system of verification if art is good or bad.
In a mysterious, puzzling, and mystical way, the true work of art arises "from out of the artist." Once released from him, it assumes its own independent life, takes on a personality, and becomes a self-sufficient, spiritually breathing subject that also leads a real material life: it is a being. It is not, therefore an indifferent phenomenon arising from chance, living out an indifferent spiritual life, but rather possesses-- like every living being-- further creative, active forces. It lives and acts and plays a part in the creation of the spiritual atmosphere that we have discussed. It is also exclusively from this inner standpoint that one must answer the question whether the work is good or bad. If it is "bad" formally, or too weak, then this form is unsuitable or too weak to produce any kind of pure, spiritual vibration within the soul.
Kandinsky's truth is every bit as true as any logical inquiry.
In Patricia Lockwood's recent review of Simon Critchley's book on mysticism, she has this to say about William James:
To read The Varieties of Religious Experience is to believe not only that God might exist but that men might be good – and more, that they may be taken at their word. He simply (it is so radical) presents us with their paragraphs. It is in every way the opposite of those pretensions we gather to ourselves as protection against irony. It is not in wordplay, in hazelnuts and hazelnots, though theology has tangled itself so much in those things. The wound of experience is presented, open; it does not need to be probed, it is believed. [...] In James there is a sense of many doors opening on dimensions; he goes between them with his lively and solemn gift, his curiosity. And what I think of as his characteristic nouns: lustre and reality. The corrugated rays coming off the first, and the second almost seeming to have human eyes.
Against Peirce's metaphsical deflation, James gives us a metaphysical plenum. Pragmatism, for James, means living in a world that is disenchanted, re-enchanted, never disenchanted, never enchanted all at once. It means living in a world of scientific rationality and base materialism alongside the energies of God, all the Gods, things older than Gods, and beings that are yet-to-come. Horkheimer's critique turns out to have some weight, James' pragmatism makes the world both too subjective and too objective, both too rational and too mystical.
As James puts it in The Varieties of Religious Experience: “Like the single drops which sparkle in the sun as they are flung far ahead of the advancing edge of a wave-crest or a flood, they show the way and are forerunners. The world is not yet with them, so they often seem in the midst of the world’s affairs to be preposterous. Yet they are impregnators of the world, vivifiers and animators of potentialities of goodness which but for them would lie forever dormant.”