Today would have been Deleuze's 100th birthday. So, here is a blog post about Deleuze's concept of transcendental empiricism.
Transcendental Empiricism connects Deleuze's book on Hume through to his last essay, "Immanence: A Life". Deleuze never stops being an empiricist, and one way to understand his project is to stay with his empiricism. This is because, for Deleuze, empiricism is both ontological and methodological. Empiricism is promise for Deleuze, and it is why that even if he is doing political philosophy, aesthetics, or metaphysics, he comes back to transcendental empiricism. Because it promises there must be some way out of here.
The Thief
Early on, Deleuze establishes that the problem of philosophy is the problem of stupidity. Who can forget his claim in Nietzsche and Philosophy that philosophy is useful for harming stupidity. But this harming stupidity is not whatever is going on in the movie Idiocracy with its obvious eugenicist overtones. Rather, stupidity is closer to Arendt's banality of evil and her charge of Eichmann's unthinking nature. As Deleuze makes clearer in Difference and Repetition, particularly chapter three, stupidity is the condition being unable to think outside of the image of thought. It is not about error, or even wrong answers. But rather, what kinds of questions can we even think of asking and forwarding? The image of thought (of which can be known by many names, such as doxa, the problematic, the historical a priori, the transcendental, but also text, desire, signs, even māyā) structures not just what are correct answers, but also what we even consider possible alternatives. And if the image of thought is all there is, then we are done. But, we know that is not all there is. We know there is creativity, novelty, and genuine change. Therefore the image of thought is not everything. There must be something pre-meditative, pre-interpretive, some thought of the outside. This is the promise of transcendental empiricism--experience, no matter how subjectified it might become, brings with the chaotic outside. The outside however is too much, too vast, too contradictory--a plenum. This is why the outside is always depicted by Deleuze as chaos and multiplicity, and drawing ourselves toward the outside is talked about in paradoxes and schizoanalysis. Because in some way the outside does not make sense, cannot make sense, interrupts the very process of sense-making.
This outside--however chaotic, however fragmentary, however dangerous--is what allows for the resistance to this order of things. One way to read Deleuze is as a long analysis of how we are trapped in a series of pre-given questions and answers (what Deleuze called stupidity), along with some sort of understanding of this outside (what we might think of as an absurd and necessary task of a cartography of chaos and change), and lastly we have the fragments of an user manual for accessing the outside, bringing back something useful, and trying to avoid the dangerous of such an intellectual mission. Deleuze's language for explaining all of this shifts throughout his career, as does his own understanding. Perhaps the most famous example is the difference between Anti-Oedipus and A Thousand Plateaus. In A-O we are told that escaping subjectification is the most important thing, and that one can never go far enough. In ATP, we are famously warned there are worse things that staying subjectified. But this why we have a constant language of becomings, pacts with strange others, dark precursors, Bergsonian intuition, Spinozian conatus. These are all methods for trying to get outside, and bring back something new. That which in What is Philosphy? is called the Chaoids, the three daughters of Chaos, which are philosophy, art and science. In other words, empiricists in their thinking-sensation are exploring the outside in order to bring back new concepts, affects and precepts, and functions.
The Joker
Micheal Hardt taught, at least briefly, in prisons. He is fond of telling one anecdote, and here is a version of it:
One semester we had a joint meeting of the Duke [graduate] students and the inmates. They prepared punch and cake for us, and we sat around and had a discussion about Foucault's Discipline and Punish.[...] The inmates would insist, "Look, whatever the prison tries to do to you, whatever the officials try to do, if you're strong, you can always keep the real you hidden inside. You can create this ungraspable core that is you, that they can never touch. Strip-searches, humiliations, anything, they can't touch it." Goffman describes the recreation of an institutional subjectivity, and they say, "No. For weak people that might be true, but not me." They had this resistance to the idea of the production of subjectivity. It seemed to them like a threat, a personal threat. That was their last line of defense. For the Duke students, of course, their interest in Foucault was in the very complete production of subjectivity by the institutions of power.
If one way of escaping the image of thought is to use empiricism to try and chart a way outside, to try and draw up a line of flight into chaos and back, there is another, less talked about, way to escape. Perhaps there is some part of us that remains outside of subjectification. Is there, as the incarcerated students put it, a core that escapes? Somethings that remains opaque from the all-seeing institutions of power? A kind of Glissantian right to opacity? Or, as the Duke students had it, are we just the complete productions of subjectivity by the institutions of power? And to the degree we have a self, it is because there are glitches and gaps in the machinery and technologies of self? Even more than his contradictory understanding of a thought from outside, Deleuze's understanding of if a thought from inside is even possible is all over the place.
One way to understand a thought from inside is as a kind of Bataillian inner experience. That is to say we in moments of mysticism, madness, ecstasy (but also in purposeful methods of dhyāna) we can still find ways out of the image of thought. That is we go into ourselves to find something outside. This is not a process of reflection, because as Deleuze and Guattari tell us in ATP: "Thought is like the Vampire; it has no image, either to constitute a model of or to copy." These experiences are still pre-interpretative, pre-mediative. The central breakdown of Artaud and the crack-up of F. Scott Fitzgerald are some of the many examples that Deleuze forwards of this kind of inner experience that escapes complete subjectification. But of course, the whole point of this understanding of inner experience is that it complicates the very notions of inside and outside. In the many foldings of Deleuze, the idea that the self is Möbius stripped becomes central. The experience of the inside becomes a way to experience the outside, so that we can get outside of the inside of the image of thought. Got it?
But that is not really an understanding of a core, is it? Quite the opposite, it is a folding, a shifting. In Deleuze's books on Leibniz and even more so, his book on Foucault, we get some sort of understanding of the self that stands outside. This is particularly clear on Deleuze's reading of volume 2 and 3 of Foucault's History of Sexuality.
But is there an inside that lies deeper than any internal world, just as the outside is farther away than any external world? The outside is not a fixed limit but amoving matter animated by peristaltic movements, folds and foldings that together make up an inside: they are not something other than the outside, but precisely the inside of the outside. The Order of Things developed this theme: if thought comes from outside, and remains attached to the outside, how come the outside does not flood into the inside, as the element that thought does not and cannot think of? The unthought is therefore not external to thought but lies at its very heart, as that impossibility of thinking which doubles or hollows out the outside. (pp. 96-97)
Of course all life is a process of breaking down, but the blows that do the dramatic side of the work – the big sudden blows that come, or seem to come, from outside – the ones you remember and blame things on and, in moments of weakness, tell your friends about, don’t show their effect all at once. There is another sort of blow that comes from within – that you don’t feel until it’s too late to do anything about it, until you realize with finality that in some regard you will never be as good a man again. The first sort of breakage seems to happen quick – the second kind happens almost without your knowing it but is realized suddenly indeed. (From the opening to F. Scott Fitzgerald's "The Crack-Up")